Études Ricoeuriennes / Ricoeur Studies
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur
<p><strong><em><span class="ILfuVd"><span class="hgKElc">É</span></span>tudes ricœuriennes / Ricœur Studies</em> (ERRS)</strong> is an electronic, open access, peer-reviewed academic journal devoted to the study of the work of Paul Ricœur. The journal was founded in 2010 by Scott Davidson, Johann Michel and George Taylor. ERRS is interdisciplinary in scope and seeks to continue Ricœur's own dialogue across the disciplines (law, political science, sociology, anthropology, history, to name only a few). ERRS invites critical appraisals and constructive extensions of Ricœur's vast oeuvre. ERRS also welcomes original contributions from the intellectual traditions (hermeneutics, phenomenology, structuralism, analytic philosophy...) and themes (memory, history, justice, recognition...) that Ricœur engaged in his work.</p><p><strong>Editorial Direction </strong>: Prof. Ernst Wolff and Prof. Jean-Luc Amalric<strong><br /></strong></p><p><strong>Editorial Secretary : </strong>Amélie Canu<strong><br /></strong></p><p><strong>Editorial Board </strong>:</p><table width="424"><tbody><tr><td>Prof. Olivier Abel</td><td>Prof. Pamela Sue Anderson</td><td>Prof. John Arthos</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Marie-France Bégué</td><td>Prof. Patrick Bourgeois</td><td>Prof. Andris Breitling</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Marc Breviglieri</td><td>Prof. Jeffrey Barash</td><td>Prof. Mireille Delbraccio</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. François Dosse</td><td>Prof. Farhang Erfani</td><td>Prof. Gaelle Fiasse</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Michael Foessel</td><td>Prof. Daniel Frey</td><td>Catherine Goldenstein</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Jerôme de Gramont</td><td>Prof. Jean Greisch</td><td>Prof. Jean Grondin</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Christina Gschwandtner</td><td>Prof. Annemie Halsema</td><td>Prof. Domenico Jervolino</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Morny Joy</td><td>Prof. Maureen Junker-Kenny</td><td>Prof. Richard Kearney</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Marc de Launay</td><td>Prof. Sabina Loriga</td><td>Prof. Patricio Andrés Mena Malet</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Todd Mei</td><td>Olivier Mongin</td><td>Prof. Mirela Oliva</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. David Pellauer</td><td>Prof. Jérôme Porée</td><td>Prof. Charles Reagan</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Myriam Revault d'Allonnes</td><td>Prof. Andreea Ritivoi</td><td>Prof. Roger Savage</td></tr><tr><td>Jean-Louis Schlegel</td><td>Prof. William Schweiker</td><td>Prof. Alison Scott- Bauman</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Nicola Stricker</td><td>Prof. Páll Skúlason</td><td>Prof. John Starkey</td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Dan Stiver</td><td>Prof. Yasuhiko Sugimura</td><td><p>Prof. George Taylor</p></td></tr><tr><td>Prof. Laurent Thevenot</td><td>Prof. Gilbert Vincent</td><td><p>Prof. Mark Wallace</p><p>Prof. Johann Michel</p></td></tr></tbody></table>University Library System, University of Pittsburghen-USÉtudes Ricoeuriennes / Ricoeur Studies2156-7808<br /><strong>Authors who publish with this journal agree to the following terms: </strong><br /><br /><ol><ol><li>The Author retains copyright in the Work, where the term “Work” shall include all digital objects that may result in subsequent electronic publication or distribution.<br /><br /></li><li>Upon acceptance of the Work, the author shall grant to the Publisher the right of first publication of the Work.<br /><br /></li><li>The Author shall grant to the Publisher and its agents the nonexclusive perpetual right and license to publish, archive, and make accessible the Work in whole or in part in all forms of media now or hereafter known under a <a href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/" target="_blank">Creative Commons 4.0 License (Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works)</a>, or its equivalent, which, for the avoidance of doubt, allows others to copy, distribute, and transmit the Work under the following conditions:<ol style="list-style-type: lower-alpha;"><li>Attribution—other users must attribute the Work in the manner specified by the author as indicated on the journal Web site;</li><li>Noncommercial—other users (including Publisher) may not use this Work for commercial purposes;</li><li>No Derivative Works—other users (including Publisher) may not alter, transform, or build upon this Work,with the understanding that any of the above conditions can be waived with permission from the Author and that where the Work or any of its elements is in the public domain under applicable law, that status is in no way affected by the license. <br /><br /></li></ol></li><li>The Author is able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the nonexclusive distribution of the journal's published version of the Work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), as long as there is provided in the document an acknowledgement of its initial publication in this journal.<br /><br /></li><li>Authors are permitted and encouraged to post online a pre-publication <em>manuscript</em> (but not the Publisher’s final formatted PDF version of the Work) in institutional repositories or on their Websites prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work. Any such posting made before acceptance and publication of the Work shall be updated upon publication to include a reference to the Publisher-assigned DOI (Digital Object Identifier) and a link to the online abstract for the final published Work in the Journal.<br /><br /></li><li>Upon Publisher’s request, the Author agrees to furnish promptly to Publisher, at the Author’s own expense, written evidence of the permissions, licenses, and consents for use of third-party material included within the Work, except as determined by Publisher to be covered by the principles of Fair Use.<br /><br /></li><li>The Author represents and warrants that:<br /><br /></li><ol style="list-style-type: lower-alpha; padding-left: 40px;"><li>the Work is the Author’s original work;</li><li>the Author has not transferred, and will not transfer, exclusive rights in the Work to any third party;</li><li>the Work is not pending review or under consideration by another publisher;</li><li>the Work has not previously been published;</li><li>the Work contains no misrepresentation or infringement of the Work or property of other authors or third parties; and</li><li>the Work contains no libel, invasion of privacy, or other unlawful matter.<br /> </li></ol><li>The Author agrees to indemnify and hold Publisher harmless from Author’s breach of the representations and warranties contained in Paragraph 6 above, as well as any claim or proceeding relating to Publisher’s use and publication of any content contained in the Work, including third-party content.</li></ol></ol>Après la « Petite Éthique » de Paul Ricœur (1990), le sens de sa révision (2001)
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur/article/view/644
<div> <div> <p class="AbstractParagraphs"><span lang="EN-GB">Paul Ricœur presents his ethical thought in two important texts: first, in studies 7, 8, and 9 of <em>Oneself as Another</em> (1990), and eleven years later (2001), in the article, “From the Moral to the Ethical and to Ethics,” in <em>Reflections on the Just</em>. As well known, the discussion in </span><em><span lang="EN-GB">Oneself as Another </span></em><span lang="EN-GB">moves from ethics to morality to practical wisdom. The present article emphasizes the implications of Ricoeur’s rethinking of this relation in his 2001 presentation. There Ricoeur inverts his </span><span lang="EN-US">order</span><span lang="EN-GB">, beginning with the morality of duty, the origin of which must be thought before the ethics of the good life, now called “anterior ethics.” Two questions are then posed: what is the basis of duty and obligation, and what is the relationship between practical wisdom and “posterior ethics,” the new title given to “practical wisdom”? Lastly, the article incorporates an essential detail Ricœur developed in his essay <em>Love and Justice</em>, with a view toward completing his most recent overview of ethics</span><span lang="EN-US">.</span></p> </div> </div>Michel RENAUD
Copyright (c) 2024 Michel RENAUD
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/
2024-08-282024-08-2815112510.5195/errs.2024.644De Rawls à Ricœur : les paradoxes de la justice
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur/article/view/658
<div> <div> <p class="AbstractParagraphs"><span lang="EN-US">The article explores Ricœur’s critical interpretation of Rawls’ theory of social justice. While Ricœur has a dialectical conception of justice (where the “good” encompasses the “just”), contrasting with Rawls’ procedural approach (where the just is defined independently of the good), Ricœur shows a strong interest in Rawls’ ideas. He situates Rawls’ project within one of the moments of the dialectic of the just: the moral moment. This dialectic arises from the aporetic nature of the just and manifests in ethical life as three paradoxes: political, legal, and socio-economic. While Rawls’ approach struggles with these paradoxes, they are the driving force of Ricœur’s approach to justice, highlighting its strength</span><span lang="EN-US">.</span></p> </div> </div>Feriel Kandil
Copyright (c) 2024 Feriel Kandil
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/
2024-08-282024-08-28151266110.5195/errs.2024.658Les apories de l'identité narrative
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur/article/view/646
<div> <div> <p class="AbstractParagraphs"><span lang="EN-US">The notion of narrative identity brings the possibility of self-identity (or<span class="apple-converted-space"> </span><em>idem</em>-identity) with that of change. But is </span><span lang="EN-US">what Ricoeur calls a “dialectical” mediation between identity and change necessary? Only if identity is supposed to exclude change, but this is not the case with identity in the most fundamental sense of the term: numerical identity. The second difficulty is that Ricoeur often seems to reduce the notions of history and narration to one another. It is hardly controversial that we are historical beings, but does this mean that our identity depends on the narratives we fashion for our histories? Finally, the third aporia lies in the primordial position Ricoeur gives to fiction in his determination of narrative identity. However, it’s not at all clear that fictional characters enjoy a genuine identity in any possible sense: e.g., contemporary theorists of reference such as Saul Kripke and David Kaplan have insisted that fictional characters possess only an appearance of identity. How, then, can we make this semblance of identity, which amounts to a bundle of more or less stable characteristics, the model for addressing the question of the status of our real identities</span><span lang="EN-US">?</span></p> </div> </div>Claude Romano
Copyright (c) 2024 Claude Romano
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/
2024-08-282024-08-28151628510.5195/errs.2024.646Comprendre Temps et récit II : du discours théorique au commentaire de Mrs Dalloway
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur/article/view/653
<div> <div> <p class="AbstractParagraphs"><span lang="EN-US">This article proposes a reading of Paul Ricœur’s <em>Time and Narrative II</em>. This book, which focuses on the idea of the configuration of time in narrative in order to ensure continuity between the prefiguration of narrative and its refiguration and also seeks to understand the specificity of fictional narrative in relation to historical narrative, is a three-dimensional discourse: philosophy, theories of narrative and major works of literature. The text poses a number of theoretical problems that will be considered here in relation to literary theory through a critical reflection informed by a reading of Virginia Woolf’s novel Mrs Dalloway</span><span lang="EN-US">.</span></p> </div> </div>Cristina Henrique da Costa
Copyright (c) 2024 Cristina Henrique da Costa
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/
2024-08-282024-08-281518610610.5195/errs.2024.653La Salade de Don Quichotte
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur/article/view/647
<div> <div> <p class="AbstractParagraphs"><span lang="EN-US">Cervantes’ <em>Don</em> <em>Quixote </em>occupies a singular place in the history of literary translation into French, at least because it has been the subject of incessant retranslations. But the book is particularly noteworthy because translation is thematized for its own sake in two places in it. By playing with the codes of the chivalry novel, Cervantes set the general framework for theoretical reflection on translation, the main tensions of which are highlighted in this paper. By internalizing its own fictional and translational origins, in an interlude straddling chapters VIII and IX, <em>Don Quixote</em> evokes both the idea of an impossible translation, but also that of translation as a particular reading modality, in which modern literature originates as a quasi-world (Ricœur) conducive to textual exchange. Finally, we show that, in so doing, Cervantes pointed unwittingly, of course, to both structuralism and the hermeneutic tradition and, ultimately, to their problematic articulation</span><span lang="EN-US">.</span></p> </div> </div>Thierry Capmartin
Copyright (c) 2024 Thierry Capmartin
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/
2024-08-282024-08-2815110712510.5195/errs.2024.647Solicitude, Emotions, and Narrative in Technology Design Ethics
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur/article/view/645
<div> <div> <p class="AbstractParagraphs"><span lang="EN-US">The </span><span lang="EN-US">first objective of this paper is to recognize the role of emotion and feeling in Ricœur’s “little ethics” and what they can further add to it, then to explore in more detail how solicitude as a virtue, and affective disposition more broadly, can contribute to a modern ethics of technology. Ultimately, emotions help us to understand technologies and technological ways of being today; Ricœur’s “little ethics”, along with his narrative theory, provide a framework for understanding the ethically salient aspects of technical practice, especially through the openness to the other demanded by solicitude, and essentially by emphasising emotion or feeling as a way of being in the world, and a mode of existence: one which is done with, if not sometimes because of, technology and technical practice</span><span lang="EN-US">.</span></p> </div> </div>Paul HayesNoel Fitzpatrick
Copyright (c) 2024 Paul Hayes, Noel Fitzpatrick
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/
2024-08-282024-08-2815112614810.5195/errs.2024.645Another in Oneself: Hybridity of the narrative identity and followability as narrative hospitality for others
https://ricoeur.pitt.edu/ojs/ricoeur/article/view/657
<div> <div> <p class="AbstractParagraphs"><span lang="EN-US">The following article investigates the hybridity of narrative identity. It explores how idem-identity and the ipse-identity interrelate through time and otherness and illustrates the process of self’s reflexive re-cognition via others. It posits that </span><span lang="EN-US">narrative</span><span lang="EN-US"> identity encompasses both private and public dimensions, requiring a co-authorship that integrates collective identities. This article argues for an ethical dimension to this identity, emphasizing the reciprocal movement between self and other. It introduces the concept of followability, which involves reconstructing narratives in a resonance relationship, fostering narrative hospitality and mutual transformation. The study concludes by proposing an eschatological perspective as a horizon for followability, enhancing narrative refiguration through future-oriented imagination</span><span lang="EN-US">.</span></p> </div> </div>Jonghyuk Chang
Copyright (c) 2024 Jonghyuk Chang
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/us/
2024-08-282024-08-2815114916110.5195/errs.2024.657